The Carolingian Galactic Polity; or Bretons IN SPACE!

Exciting times are afoot! Specifically, I’m part-way through a deep-dive into non-Weberian theories of the state. There’s some background to this: back in 2014, I was part of a team organising a conference on the Carolingian frontier, and my pet frontier was ninth-century Brittany. I have subsequently published about this, but I never did get to grips with one key question: was Brittany part of the West Frankish kingdom, and if so, how? King Salomon (say) had various symbolic and ritual bonds of submission with Charles the Bald, but would either or both of them thought of themselves as being members of the same polity; and if so, how, and at what point in their relationship? I’d filed these questions in the musty cardboard boxes at the back of my head. Then, at this year’s IMC, I went to see John Latham Sprinkle talk about the Byzantine Empire as something called a ‘segmentary state’, and it was one of the most exciting papers I’ve ever been to. John kindly gave me a reading list, and I’ve been beavering away at the reading ever since. This blog post, then, is a first effort to outline what a ‘segmentary state’/’mandala polity’ is, and how useful it is to scholars of the early middle ages generally and Carolingianists specifically.

Let’s start at the beginning. From at least the middle of the twentieth century, anthropologists, and historians of Southeast Asia (amongst others, but these groups make up the bulk of my reading list) have been trying to escape from, or at least adapt to different circumstances, Weberian models of the polity conceived of as Eurocentric, and a number of models have been developed which, if not identical, at the very least overlap closely. In 1956, Aidan Southall wrote a study of the Alur of what is now Uganda, and for his study developed a model of the ‘segmentary state’. In an article in the ‘70s, he championed a version of this model explicitly for comparative purposes, and in that article he gave a simple one-sentence definition of the ‘segmentary state’: ‘one in which the spheres of ritual suzerainty and political sovereignty do not coincide. The former extends widely towards a flexible, changing periphery. The latter is confined to the central, core domain.’ However, I find this definition too simple, and prefer the list of criteria that he gave in his original monograph. There, he defined a ‘segmentary state’ as one in which:

1) Territorial sovereignty is recognised but limited and relative, forming a series of zones in which authority fades out the further away you go, shading into ritual hegemony.

2) There is a central government but also numerous peripheral foci of administration over which the centre exercises only limited control.

3) There are specialised administrators at the centre, which are repeated on a limited scale at these peripheral foci.

4) The centre has a limited monopoly on legitimate force, but the peripheral foci have a more restricted range of legitimate force options as well.

5) Several levels of peripheral foci can be distinguished, arranged pyramidally, these being reduced images of the centre.

6) The more peripheral a subordinate authority is the more likely it can change from one power pyramid to another, and some can have political standing in several adjacent power pyramids.

That’s a lot of stuff in one go, but hopefully turning to the south-east Asian side will make it a bit clearer. In south-east Asian studies, a very similar model of the pre-modern polity is associated with the work of Stanley Tambiah, who described what he called a ‘mandala polity’. Based on the Buddhist conception of a mandala, Tambiah proposed that south-east Asian polities could be described in terms of overlapping and/or concentric circles. Thus, the archetypal ‘mandala polity’ can be diagrammed as such:

source: Tambiah, ‘Galactic Polity’, p. 505, fig. 1.

Schematically, we have an imperial centre (a royal capital such as the city of Pagan or Ayutthaya), surrounded by a core of inner provinces ruled over by subordinate rulers, and an outer periphery of ‘tributary’ kingdoms ruled over by yet smaller-scale rulers. Each of these levels reproduces the one above it on a smaller scale: Shan princelings in the Burmese highlands copied the imperial palace at Mandalay, and tiny local Kachin chiefs copied the Shan copying the imperial centre. The power of the centre ebbed and flowed, and there was never only one centre. The ‘mandala polity’ is also known as the ‘solar’ or ‘galactic polity’, to sharpen this metaphor. The idea here is that the imperial centre acts as a ‘sun’, exerting a gravitational influence on outlying ‘satellites’ which is stronger the closer a satellite is. However, the ‘satellites’ also exert their own gravitational pull; and a ‘satellite’ can be under the effects of more than one degree of pull at once. Finally, the system ‘pulsates’, such that the pull of a ‘sun’ can decrease substantially and one of the outlying ‘planets’ can increase enough for it to form a new imperial centre. These ideas have been developed in numerous directions, but I particularly want to point out the work of James C. Scott, who adds two main insights: 1) that the pull exerted by a ‘sun’ is not a linear function of distance, but is heavily affected by geography which is not amenable to state control (in his case, mountains; but he notes that oceans would also fit the bill); and 2) that the effects of overlapping ‘gravitational pulls’ can work out in quite different ways, from simple dual vassalage to outright cancelling each other out.

These two ideas, the ‘segmentary state’ and the ‘galactic polity’ do have some differences – for instance, the ‘segmentary state’’s focus on genealogical lineage and the explicit ties of the ‘galactic polity’ to Buddhist cosmology – but in terms of what I find interesting about them, the similarities are much stronger and more interesting than the dissimilarities. Both of them give a model of the pre-modern polity which, in my reading, have five key points:

1)    they focus on centres, not borders.

2)    These centres are layered: there is legitimate conceptual space for lower-level rulers to exercise authority in qualitatively similar ways to higher-level ones.

3)    Indeed, authority is actively imitative: lower-level rulers consciously model themselves on higher-level ones.

4)    However, authority is not exclusive: subordinate authorities can have political relationships to multiple higher-level rulers.

5)    Finally, there is a firm role for the esoteric: the symbolic and ritual dimensions of rule are as important as Weberian indicators of sovereign control.

I am, of course, wildly unqualified to comment on how well these models actually work within their own disciplinary contexts. Do they, though, work for the Carolingian world, or can they be adapted thereto? Let’s go through the points in order.

Centres

Broadly speaking, this one gets a thumbs up. I don’t want to deny the importance of borders in the Carolingian world and the early Middle Ages more broadly – not least because Sam has already written about that subject on this very website – but I’ve always found thinking about centres not edges more helpful for the Carolingian period. In this case, Southall’s ‘segmentary state’ is probably the more helpful version. The focus on cities in the Southeast Asian material doesn’t have much Carolingian parallel. Sure, there are your Aachens and your Compiègnes, but ‘capital cities’ are conspic. by their a. Southall’s focus on the person of chiefs seems more helpful here. In fact, this point seems like it would pair up with medievalist ideas of königsnahe to feed back in to wider discussions of these concepts. Both models have a linearly geographic focus, which the Carolingian world raises questions about: it would be hard to argue that, say, Toulouse had more königsnahe than the Spanish March even though Toulouse was closer to West Frankish kingship centres. A analytical emphasis on the strength of the ‘gravitational’ pull rather than the geographic arrangement of the planets would help here. (Scott does hint towards this in his discussion of the ‘friction of distance’ over difficult terrain; but ‘political distance’, if I can put it like that, doesn’t necessarily require logistically difficult geographical space.) This emphasis would also help when dealing with something else the Southeast Asian historians don’t seem to have to deal with: itinerancy. Medievalists have been dealing with patterns of royal movement for a very long time, but whilst Louis the Pious or Charles the Simple’s limited mobility can fit relatively neatly into a ‘solar polity’ model, something like Louis IV’s 941/942 journey across the length and breadth of the West Frankish kingdom threatens to turn our image from a solar system into a billiard table unless we model political relations very abstractly.

Layers

This point is probably the least important qua the Carolingians, because I think it’s originally designed to draw a distinction with a Weberian ‘monopoly of legitimate violence’ which we don’t think the Carolingians had anyway. There is more to say about this, but I think it’s better placed under the next point:

Imitation

Here consideration of Carolingian society takes us in two opposite directions. On one hand, as Jinty Nelson has pointed out, kingship was special. The unique connection forged by ceremonies like unction gives the king a relationship with the numinous that then becomes the key aspect of his power: a count is legitimate because he can access the font of legitimacy which is kingship. There is thus a qualitative chasm between the king and even high-authority territorial officials like the Neustrian marchio. However, on the other hand, I think that there is room for exploration here. Claims such as ‘the tenth-century English state was the most Carolingian kingdom of the earlier Middle Ages’ are well-known, and I think that the Danish kingdom might have been adopting elements of Carolingian rule as well. Sometimes, this was actively pursued by Carolingian kings: Charles the Bald’s dealings with the Breton ruler Salomon, including offering him Frankish-style royal regalia, were part of an attempt to make Brittany easier to control by channelling Breton rulership into Carolingian models. Equally, imitation of *non-royal* Carolingian rule would repay inquiry: I have an article in preparation discussing this in the case of Normandy, for instance, which we’ll go into more in a future post.

Exclusivity

This is one the places where the mandala polity not only fits well, but has its strongest explanatory power. I’ve mentioned before that Frisia is peculiar, partially because it’s in both the Frankish and the Danish spheres of influence. The work of IJssennagger and Croix has stressed Frisia’s place within a cultural continuum, its liminal status. This rhymes beautifully with a mandala polity model: Frisia is within the ‘orbits’ of both the Carolingians and the Danes. Thus, Roric of Dorestad – for example – can be conceptualised as an integral part of both ‘solar systems’. This then helps us explain some of the stranger things about Frisia. For instance, we recently discussed how Frisia (like Normandy) had Carolingian-style counts, but Roric himself was never (unlike the Norman rulers) characterised as a Carolingian-style supermagnate, but rather as a Danish king. But this makes sense: Frisia was part of the Danish kingdom and simultaneously part of the Lotharingian one, and so its political culture reflects not just both, but the interactions between both as well. There are other examples here: in the tenth century, for instance, parts of western Lotharingia were in the mandalas of both the West Frankish and Ottonian kingdoms (and this might be, as Scott discusses, an instance where the result was two sovereignties cancelling each other out), and Brittany, Normandy and Flanders could probably be conceptualised as being part of the English mandala too.

Esotericism

Finally, we come to the role played by the symbolic and ritual dimensions of rule. Here, let’s go back to Brittany, where I started. I was having trouble conceptualising Brittany because it’s hard to understand Frankish influence in the region when viewed through a Weberian prism. The Carolingians didn’t rule Brittany, and their power in the region was only ever manifest through actual invasions (and in Charles the Bald’s time, at least, the odds of the Bretons winning was pretty good). However, Brittany was not a peer polity. It was – somehow – subordinate, and that subordination tended to be expressed precisely in these symbolic dimensions, such as Charles the Bald making Erispoë his son-in-law or Alan the Great adopting Carolingian styles of rule. Looking at it with a ‘mandala polity’ model in mind, though, Brittany comes into relatively clear focus as an example of an outer-ring polity of the Carolingian mandala. There are, of course, nuances here (as I’ve written about in the past, there were forces in Breton politics which actively rejected associations with the Carolingians, and I feel like the model needs to provide conceptual space for conscious rejection of models of rule as well as conscious imitation). Nonetheless, the Breton case shows quite clearly that this is good to think with.

Prima facie, then, we have a good case for the application of a ‘mandala polity’ model to the Carolingian world. I am, of course, about as far from being an expert on southeast Asia or Africa as you could get, so it’s quite possible that I have misunderstood the models. If and when I use them more in my work, I will certainly chop and change them to better fit the specifics of my research’s time and place. For now, though, I leave you on two questions. First, if you’re from one of the fields which generated these models, what have I missed? What should I be reading about this? Second, if you’re from my own field, what do you think of this model as a tool for understanding?

14 thoughts on “The Carolingian Galactic Polity; or Bretons IN SPACE!

  1. I need to grab some references from you about this, Fraser. The mandala one in particular seems very useful to me, though I also see why you think the segmentary model might work better than it for you. (Stupid name, though; segments all meet in the centre, usually. ‘Onion polities’ would be more like what you describe.)

    My only contrubution here is that there is a limited Western scholarship which has tried to explain the organisation of polities without borders, by instead framing them as connected nodes on a map, the zones between which remain undefined – though an important modifier might be that they obviously could be defined, if there was pressure so to do. The person I first saw doing this was Élisabeth Zadora-Rio, “From Gregory of Tours to the French Revolution: the fabric of parish networks and parish boundaries in Touraine” (unpublished presentation at the Institute of Historical Research, University of London, 16th May 2007), which doesn’t help you much, and I don’t know if she’s said it elsewhere. But after some investigation I found that the source of this kind of thinking about polities is supposed to be Monica L. Smith, “Territories, Corridors, and Networks: A Biological Model for the Premodern State” in Complexity Vol. 12 (Los Angeles 2007), pp. 28–35, DOI: 10.1002/cplx.20173. This is one of those things I haven’t read, but in case you want to I offer it up as a further thinking tool.

    Like

    1. In fairness to the name ‘segmentary polity’, I understand it derives from the segmentary lineage, although apparently whether or not we’re actually dealing with segmentary lineages here is up for debate…

      I read Smith’s article, thank you! It’s a concise and clear piece of work, but what particularly struck me was that it’s doing almost exactly the same thing as Müller-Mertens’ idea of royal heartlands separated by transit zones. About half the time, I think that translating classic German historiography into cool cutting-edge social science and/or anthropological terms is just changing the names (and then half the time they go all legal history and it throws me right back to the nineteenth century, but hey…).

      Like

  2. I’ve come across the very ideas you speak of in a different way, by reading Victor Lieberman’s “Strange Parallels: Southeast Asia in a Global Context, 800 – 1830”, in which he in effect does the same comparison as you but in reverse – he’s a specialist on medieval and early modern Burma comparing southeast Asia to the Carolingian Empire and Capetian France. And I think the solar polity/ segmented state model works pretty well for the Carolingian Empire, or for that matter Ottonian Germany and tenth century Anglo-Saxon England.

    Like

    1. Oddly enough, I’m actually in the mdidle of reading volume II of Lieberman’s work. It’s interesting enough, but I can’t help but feeling like his framework of comparison is so loose that he could compare *anything* (yes, polities will get bigger or smaller if you look over a five-hundred year period as he does!).

      Like

      1. I think what he’s doing is a little bit more subtle than that. He’s of course reacting to two contrasting historiographical tendencies – for premodern Asianists to see political and cultural history as basically cyclical, and for premodern Europeanists to see linear development towards modern nation-states from the ninth to the nineteenth centuries. And like anything involving comparing Europe and East/ South/ Southeast Asia, there’s the shadow of the great divergence looming.

        I think the basic thrust of his comparison is that across the Eurasian periphery, you can see in the latter half of the first millennium these states from which borrow from a foreign high culture and universal religion – the charter polities. By about 1300, they’ve all been destroyed/ internally fragmented/ fallen into interregnum. But subsequent polities in the and region claim legitimacy from them, build on the administrative, legal, cultural and ideological foundations they left them and become more politically and culturally integrated than before. Further periods of interregnum and reconstruction follow in cycles, but they get progressively shorter with each cycle. And thus by the beginning of the nineteenth century, we have strong states and a burgeoning sense of nationhood in all the cases. Lieberman also tried to argue that the similar timings of the cycles in all these cases may be linked to global forces like climate change.

        So ultimately I’d say his argument is a bit more subtle. But still, it narrowly veers off falling into the pitfalls of when you try to do comparative history on that kind of geographical scale over a millennium of history. Either you end up just highlighting differences, or really basic or superficial similarities, both of which make you question the point of the comparison. For a comparison to be really illuminating, ideally there needs to be enough deep similarities and enough profound differences to get you to think harder about the case study you yourself specialise in. I think in Lieberman’s own view, he’s achieved that by comparing his own mainland Southeast Asian polities to France, Russia, Japan, India, Indonesia etc. I think he was onto something as well. But you may think quite differently.

        Like

      2. Well, I know I’m caricaturing him by focussing on territorial expansion (but not *that* much, he still has graphs like it proves anything); but my ultimate point, that he’s not comparing like with like, I stand by. Even his basic idea of the ‘charter polity’ doesn’t play the same in his areas of comparison. In the Frankish world, he elides Romano-Gaulish, Merovingian and Carolingian, for instance. But probably the biggest question mark is Kievan Rus’, where he goes ‘ah, Byzantines!’, and one is left to wonder ‘but what about the Khazars/Latins/Arabs/Slavs?’ If you like, when I eventually finish the monstrous tome I can do a review here…

        Liked by 1 person

  3. Obviously, the other critique, which Lieberman denies and Alan Strathern agrees he’s avoided, is that he’s fallen into a kind of Whiggish determinism

    Like

  4. That’s a really good point. I’ve thought about how does the charter polity model work when there are polities borrowing political and governmental ideas from lord of different polities and claiming legitimacy from many of them or none of them. Norman Sicily seems to me like a good case in point, or the Seljuk and Mongol Empires and their many successor states – who exactly is their charter polity?

    As for “graphs don’t prove anything” – well I guess that’s most big history out the window then. I think graphs, statistics and other quantitive approaches are useful for premodern history (and other periods in which statistics have to be inferred because no official ones existed), in so far as you’re honest and upfront about how the data is being collected, which maybe Lieberman (or rather the various people whose studies he cites) aren’t

    Like

  5. And for some things, I’d agree that statistical approaches just don’t work. Like I can’t think how you’d quantify the state capacity of the Carolingian and Ottonian empires, as per the Ian Morris school of comparative premodern global history

    Like

Leave a comment